As absorbed as we are in our speculations about Jefferson and Hemings, a
skeptic might well wonder whether an absolute verification of the relationship
would alter our understanding of the one member of the founding generation who
still lives most vividly in our historical imagination. Obviously we would have
to adjust our views of the "character" of the "inner Jefferson," hitherto
deployed to support a conclusion opposite to the one that will now be
sustained. Obviously, too, we would have to wonder how Jefferson could allow
his children by Sally to disappear into a sort of netherworld of free society
without providing his posterity with the full measure of liberty they deserved.
No doubt the recent findings will help keep the Jefferson industry thriving
well into the new millennium.
Yet what else does the Jefferson-Hemings relationship really add to the basic
problem that has confronted us all along, which is simply to reconcile
Jefferson's egalitarian commitments with the reality of his life as a
slaveholder and his inability to discipline his reckless expenditures in the
principled cause of emancipating his own slaves? As much as the relationship
complicates and enlarges the problem of understanding Jefferson's private
life, including the psychology of slaveholding, it does not fundamentally
alter the essential public dilemma. Jefferson professed to hate slavery first
and foremost for its effects on the republican citizen, but also, in more
modest degree, for its effects on the slave; he drafted a bill for emancipation
that corresponded with the best enlightened opinion of his age; he publicly
affirmed that the freed slaves deserved settlement in a country of their own.
Yet he never emancipated any slaves but those of the Hemings family; he never
agitated for enactment of the bill he had drafted; he reacted with the deepest
alarm to the slave revolt in Santo Domingo and to the growth of a (somewhat)
more militant antislavery sentiment in the United States; and his notion of
exactly where the freed slaves might be resettled continually receded as his
"empire for liberty" progressively expanded. For the nineteenth-century South,
his legacy included the flirtation with nullification in the Kentucky
Resolutions of 1798 and the avowal of a proto-scientific theory of racial
inferiority in his Notes on the State of Virginia-- both foreshadowing
critical elements of the new militance the South would project as slavery came
under renewed and more fervent assault.
For the historian, it will not do to lump Jefferson's failings together under a
valedictory judgment of hypocrisy. After all, hypocrisy is only a
characterization of how we act, not an explanation of the sources of our
actions. Nor is there much advantage to be gained by pursuing Jefferson with
the sort of prosecutorial zeal exemplified in the work of Paul Finkelman. True,
Finkelman and other likeminded critics have performed yeoman service by
demonstrating just how easily Jefferson subordinated his ostensible abhorrence
of slavery to more pressing considerations, both public and private. Yet does
that disturbing evidence truly warrant the conclusion that "no one bore a
greater responsibility for that failure [to place the nation on the road to
liberty for all] than the author of the Declaration of Independence--the Master
of Monticello"? Given the depth of the southern commitment to the peculiar
institution as the bedrock of its economic, legal, social, and moral order, and
the fact that its abolition ultimately required the outside intervention made
possible only by the Civil War, it beggars the imagination to see how the
engaged opposition to slavery that Jefferson admittedly never mounted would
have made any difference in the fate of slavery. Judgments of moral
responsibility and political agency are not always interchangeable.
Yet they are always troubling, and never more so to historians than when they
feel impelled to encourage their students to suspend the impulse to judge in
the interest of cultivating the need to understand. The one occasion on which I
regularly confront our Jefferson problem comes when I make "Thomas Jefferson
and the American Dilemma" the subject of the lecture that closes my course on
colonial and revolutionary America. In that capacity, I act more as a teacher
than a scholar; or rather, I try to bring my perspectives as a scholar of the
eighteenth century to bear on my vocation of a teacher. As a scholar, it is not
especially important to me to judge the morality of the actors of the past.
Those judgments, if one wishes to make them, come easily and are not very
challenging; explaining the sources of the acts committed is more difficult. As
a teacher, however, I feel an obligation not only to answer my students'
natural concern--even anxiety--to know how to think about Jefferson but, more
important, to challenge their natural presumption that the moral values of our
own enlightened age are superior to those of the Age of Enlightenment that
Jefferson helped to illuminate.
In casting my Jefferson lecture in these terms, I confess to being much
influenced by a passage that Gordon Wood wrote about the efforts of our mutual
teacher, Bernard Bailyn, to write a "tragic" history of the American Revolution
that would deal fairly with the most interesting of its real "losers": Thomas
Hutchinson, penultimate royal governor of Massachusetts. Here Wood argues that
Americans do not really want to hear about the unusability and pastness of the
past or about the latent limitations within which people in the past were
obliged to act. They do not want to hear about the blindness of people in the
past or about the inescapable boundaries of their action. Such a history has no
immediate utility and is apt to remind us of our own powerlessness, of our own
inability to control events and predict the future.
The discipline of history, Wood continues, does not fully share the common
project of other social sciences. Where these disciplines try to breed
confidence in managing the future, the discipline of history tends to inculcate
skepticism about people's ability to order their destinies at will. History
that reveals the utter differentness and discontinuity of the past tends to
undermine that crude instrumental and presentist use of the past that Americans
have especially been prone to. Arid history that shows that the best-laid plans
of people in the past often went awry and that most people struggled against
forces which they never clearly understood or over which they had little
control tends to dampen that naive conquer-the-future spirit that Americans
above all other peoples possess.
And yet, Wood concludes, it is only by understanding those limitations-- and
not by imposing arbitrary degrees of freedom that the past never really
enjoyed--that we can understand what "makes true freedom and moral choice--and
wisdom--possible."
What draws us to Jefferson--and what most troubles us about him--is that our
Jefferson problem embodies the incompatible poles of historical consciousness
that Wood identifies. That Jefferson was embedded in a vicious institution that
he inherited but had not created goes without saying; that his doubts about it
fell far short of what was demanded or morally correct is just as apparent. Yet
who better represents the American conviction that the past is something from
which we can be liberated--indeed should be liberated--than Jefferson? There is
more wit and irony in Franklin; a more prudent accounting of the possibilities
and perils of popular government in Madison; a more realistic grasp of public
policy and foreign relations in Hamilton; and a more insightful understanding
of human nature in John Adams. But Jefferson speaks to us as the great
optimist, the apostle of equality and democracy, the believer in the power of
reason and the opponent of superstition and hidebound tradition. It is
Jefferson who tells us we should have confidence in our own judgment, when his
friend Madison warns us--as he warned Jefferson-- that the play of public
opinion on politics has to be carefully checked, that people more often act out
of impulsive passion or selfish interest than a prudent regard for their own or
the public good. As Wood has elsewhere noted, none of his contemporaries was
more optimistic, or more inclined to prefer the promise of the future to the
errors of the past. "He was a virtual Pollyanna about everything," Wood
observes; he "had little understanding of man's capacity for evil and had no
tragic sense whatsoever." Hence Jefferson embodied, even helped to create, that
very impoverishment of a historical sense that Wood decries--but which we
arguably need to apply if we are ever to come to grips with our Jefferson
problem. It is precisely the difficulty we experience in looking at Jefferson
in this way that makes his failure to come to grips with the problem of slavery
so troubling. If Jefferson, with his belief in reason and equality and
progress, could do no better, then what could be expected of the rest of
American society?
I have come to suspect--although I cannot prove--that Jefferson understood this
quandary better than we have realized. Far from dismissing the contradiction
between Jefferson's public condemnation of slavery and the possessive
individualism of his own slaveholding as rank hypocrisy, I now regard his
inability to imagine how whites and blacks could ever coexist as an act of
moral honesty. Having looked into his own heart (again) and seen the depth of
the prejudice that resided there, how could he have imagined that his
countrymen would prove more enlightened?
Treating Jefferson not as a hypocrite or slacker but as someone grappling with
questions he could solve neither intellectually nor morally may help us to
think anew about that passage in his writings which disturbs us most: the
discourse on racial difference in Query XIV of the Notes on the State of
Virginia. Jefferson opened his discussion of the logic of linking his
proposed scheme of gradual emancipation with a plan to colonize the freed
population elsewhere by noting that "It will probably be asked, Why not retain
and incorporate the blacks into the state, and thus save the expence of
supplying, by importation of white settlers, the vacancies they will leave?"
Jefferson initially answered this rhetorical question in a single, remarkably
direct if grimly pessimistic sentence: "Deep rooted prejudices entertained by
the whites; ten thousand recollections, by the blacks, of the injuries they
have sustained; new provocations; the real distinctions which nature has made;
and many other circumstances, will divide us into parties, and produce
convulsions which will probably never end but in the extermination of the one
or the other race." What Jefferson was arguing, in effect, was that this
relationship was already so tainted, indeed poisoned, that it could never be
made right; that the currents of mutual fear and justifiable resentment were
likely to run so deep and strong that no stable society could ever be
reconstructed with this disturbed history as its foundation--much less a
republican society requiring strong bonds of fraternity to provide the cohesion
that an absent aristocracy would not be available to offer.
Had Jefferson stopped there, or merely elaborated this point, we could still
fault him for a lack of remorse and a failure of moral nerve, but we would also
have to credit his willingness to confront the problem of creating a biracial
society with a painful if disturbing honesty. But Jefferson did not stop there.
He immediately plunged on to offer a further point: "To these objections, which
are political, may be added others, which are physical and moral." From here
Jefferson quickly descended into his discussion of the physical and
intellectual differences that must long discourage the free white and black
citizens of one polity from ever coexisting on conditions of equality. The
account Jefferson offers, however, is frankly a mess. From a brief speculation
about the possible physical sources of differences in complexion, he quickly
passes on to a merely aesthetic opinion about the relative beauty and
expressiveness of the two races, the one capable of changing color to reveal
emotion, the other "veil[ed]" in an "eternal monotony" of "the countenances."
Then Jefferson recovers and returns to "other physical distinctions," which
turn out to offer a rather loosely defined category of analysis, including some
extraordinarily subjective impressions about the emotional state of Africans.
Some of the observations are downright foolish. First Jefferson notes that
blacks "seem to require less sleep," being inclined to stay awake "for the
slightest amusements"; then, a few sentences later, he illustrates the
observation that "their existence appears to participate more of sensation than
reflection" by associating it with "their disposition to sleep when abstracted
from their diversions, and unemployed in labour." What else were they supposed
to do in the intervals between the labor demanded by their master and the
casual leisure they expropriated for themselves: crack open copies of The
Iliad or Tristram Shandy, or manuals of personal improvement--and to
what end? A further comparison of the poetry of Phyllis Wheatley and Ignatius
Sancho with the artistic accomplishments of the slaves of antiquity also seems
like an extended digression.
From our vantage point, we have good reason to wish that Jefferson might have
allowed a sense of discretion to get the better part of his intellectual valor.
Yet the confusions of this passage instruct us to read it with some care. For
starters, it is essential to understand that Jefferson's foray into a
proto-scientific racism was made in defense not of slavery but of emancipation.
That by itself distinguishes it significantly from the more virulent
expressions of racism that would be offered in later generations, for then
observations of racial difference were more commonly made to explain why
enslavement was in fact a logical and natural condition for an entire people.
Jefferson's concern is rather with explaining the problem that emancipation of
a racially distinct population would pose for the future of republican
citizenship. Moreover, by shuffling awkwardly between different modes of
comparison and analysis, Jefferson conveys his self-conscious embarrassment
about the implications of the position he is tentatively espousing, and this
becomes even more manifest when Jefferson closes his discussion on a note of
uncertainty. The conclusion he is suggesting, Jefferson warns us, "must be
hazarded with great diffidence," not least because its acceptance might work to
"degrade a whole race of men from the rank in the scale of beings which their
Creator may perhaps have given them." Jefferson then undermines his conclusion
even further by questioning the basis of his own reasoning. "To our reproach it
must be said, that though for a century and a half we have had under our eyes
the races of black and of red men, they have never yet been viewed by us as
subjects of natural history." In other words, as plausible as everything
Jefferson has just alleged about racial difference may be, it is little more
than speculation resting on an incomplete and inadequate empirical
foundation.
This impression of Jefferson's intellectual embarrassment draws further
corroboration from the other section of the Notes on the State of Virginia
addressed to the "particular customs and manners that may happen to be
received in that state." It is not self-evident that Jefferson needed to answer
that query by discussing the effect of slavery on the character of the free
citizenry. Surely that broad heading could have sustained other possible
answers that would have skirted the slavery question entirely--as if blacks
were merely the objects of white control, not active participants in society.
Instead, Jefferson invokes slavery as a fundamental threat to republican
citizenship, and in terms that simultaneously elevate the subject race to the
condition of a people capable of freedom. 'And with what execration should the
statesman be loaded, "Jefferson asks, "who permitting one half the citizens to
trample on the rights of the other, transforms those into despots, and these
into enemies, destroys the morals of the one part [the masters], and the amor
patriae of the other [the slaves]." To speak of the enslaved as the other half
of the citizenry, possessing rights at least in potentia, is a
revealing usage, and so is the concession that "love of country" is something
that slaves can be desired to possess but not expected to acquire. This
language echoes one of the opening sentences of the earlier discussion of
emancipation, where Jefferson imagines how the preparations for freedom will
end. When the younger members of the enslaved race reach the appointed age
(eighteen for women, twenty-one for men), "they should be colonized to such
place as the circumstances of the time should render most proper, sending them
out with arms, implements of household and of the handicraft arts, feeds, pairs
of the useful domestic animals, &c." --- and further, those making this
colonization possible should also take care "to declare them a free and
independent people." The echo of 1776 is unmistakable, for what the Declaration
of Independence finally declared was that the colonies were now "Free and
Independent States." A truly free and independent people following the example
of 1776 should not, of course, have independence declared for it, but declare
it for itself, making its own Lockean appeal to heaven because slavery, by
Locke's own terms, cannot be established as a hereditary condition. That was a
prospect that Jefferson, fearful of slave rebellion, could conceive but not
countenance. Yet Jefferson's doubts about the capacities of a freed population
to be integrated as equal citizens in a republican polity cannot completely
outweigh his recognition that they were equally entitled, as a people, to
reclaim the rights of self-government their enslavement had denied them.
In both queries, Jefferson's brief for emancipation takes an avowedly political
cast, resting on the dual assumption that just as blacks cannot be expected to
take the part of equal citizens, so whites reared in the habits of domination
cannot be expected to acquire the attributes desired of republican citizens.
Yet in the later query, Jefferson strikes an entirely different and surprising
note. Now when he "tremble[s] for my country," it is divine, not civil justice
that he invokes, conjuring the order of a morally governed universe where
neither a mechanistic deity nor a politically correct ultimate reality reigns,
but a justice-dispensing God. If not quite a God of revelation or miracles--for
what miracle could rescue Americans from this sin.?--it is still an almighty
clothed in the mantle of the Old and New Testament, and ominously capable of
intervening in human history to permit "a revolution in the wheel of fortune"
through an act of "supernatural influence!" Lay this passage aside Lincoln's
second inaugural, which pronounces the sentence that God has just (and justly)
executed on both parties to the Civil War as "true and righteous
altogether," and their symmetry is perfectly complementary. So is the deeper
irony linking their authors: two men who had escaped the blinders and shackles
of doctrinal creed or denominational loyalty, yet who had absorbed the language
of a Protestant moralism and who understood its hold on the consciences of
their countrymen.
The way in which Jefferson's troubled and troubling treatment of slavery and
race in these passages implicates his commitments to equality, self-government,
and the rights of conscience provides the larger context within which, I
believe, Americans need to reflect on the complexity of the Jeffersonian
legacy. It is to restoring this complexity that I now turn.
home ·
view the report ·
is it true? ·
the jefferson enigma ·
the slaves' story ·
mixed race america
special video reports ·
discussion ·
links ·
quiz ·
chronology ·
gene map
interviews ·
synopsis ·
tapes ·
teacher's guide ·
press
FRONTLINE ·
pbs online ·
wgbh
web site copyright WGBH educational foundation
|