|
As Professor Schulhofer suggests, almost every defense of plea negotiation depends on the assumption that defendants will be well-represented.2 Apologists for plea bargaining draw pictures of well-informed defendants, advised by capable attorneys, making rational assessments of surrender and gain.3 These apologists know that, were they to peer into the pit, they often would find their assumptions unjustified. Nevertheless, they regard the defective performance of lawyers as exogenous to a plea bargaining system. In their view, inadequate lawyers are as likely to appear and work their mischief in one system as another; whether their cases are bargained or tried is immaterial.4 Although these observers condemn departures from their idealized models as abuses, they evaluate the institution of plea bargaining by examining how the process might work with Earl Warren as the prosecutor, Socrates as the defense attorney, and Solomon as the trial judge. These observers wear blinders. They are somewhat like the people who once proclaimed that monarchy is a marvelous form of government so long as the king is good. Although apologists for plea negotiation usually recognize that the king may not be good, they argue that no system can be better than the people who administer it.
I
My principal goal in this paper is to demonstrate that institutional
arrangements make a difference and that the performance of lawyers is
not exogenous. A regime of plea negotiation lends itself to ineffective
assistance and aggravates its harmful consequences in at least six ways
that an adjudicative system5 does not.6
First, like other people, defense attorneys like money. A plea
bargaining system subjects these attorneys to powerful financial
temptations to disregard their clients' interests. For obvious practical
reasons, privately retained defense attorneys usually collect their fees
in advance; and once an attorney has pocketed his fee, his economic
interests lie in disposing of the case as rapidly as possible. The most
rapid way to dispose of a case is usually to enter a bargained plea. A
similar contlict of interest besets some appointed attorneys -- those who
receive small statutory payments for every case in which they appear.
The statutory compensation is never a great reward for conducting a
two-day trial; but for many lawyers, the burdens of representing the
indigent become tolerable when these burdens consist of a brief
conference with the client, a brief conference with the prosecutor, and
a brief courtroom colloquy before a negotiated plea is accepted.7
Second, apart from the desire to make money, attorneys like to
minimize work. Plea negotiation offers defense attorneys a more
comfortable way of life than does adjudication. As salaried lawyers
whose compensation does not depend on the ways in which their cases are
resolved, public defenders are not subject to the same economic
temptations as private defense attorneys. Nevertheless, all lawyers are
subject to the temptation to promote their own convenience at the
expense of their clients. As with the economic temptations noted above,
the danger is not so much deliberate betrayal as warped judgment and
excessive use of shortcuts. As one judge noted, "It is easier to sit in
an overstuffed chair drinking coffee than to stand in the courtroom
trying cases."8 It is also easier to banter with prosecutors about kids,
lakehouses and justice than to march into the field to learn the facts
or into the library to learn the law.
Somewhat similar conflicts of interest would influence the
performance of defense attorneys in an adjudicative system. There are a
variety of ways to bluff, cut corners, and "wing it" when a case is
tried. Nevertheless, the trial process constrains the ability of lawyers
to shrug off most forms of hard work as unnecessary. At trial, an
attorney must at least listen to the prosecution's witnesses and decide
whether and how to cross-examine them. Even if the attorney has
conducted no pretrial investigation, his client may have suggested some
defense witnesses (including the client himself). The attorney must
either call these witnesses to testify or explain to his client why he
has not. In addition, the attorney must participate in the formulation
of the court's instructions, argue to the jury, and more. An attorney
who wished to appear competent in performing these visible tasks would
be likely to investigate the facts before trial, speak to his witnesses,
research the relevant law and prepare in other ways. He would not have
an easy way to conclude his representation in minutes and rationalize
his lack of vigorous advocacy as the best possible representation of his
client.
In a typical shop or factory, some employees work harder than others,
but the possibility of defective performance on the job does not suggest
that it is immaterial whether the manager of the shop or factory
requires its employees to report for work. Similarly, the temptations to
cut corners that defense attorneys would experience in an adjudicative
system cannot be equated with the more powerful conflicts of interest
that confront them in our plea bargaining system.
Third, like other people, attorneys like to be liked and to enjoy
good relationships with co-workers. This personal interest, like the
others, can lead defense attorneys to represent their clients less
vigorously. In a plea bargaining system, prosecutors and trial
judges -- the group with whom a defense attorney works every day -- are
likely to become a more important constituency than the attorney's more
transient clients.9 As with the other temptations that I have mentioned,
scholars could write treatises about this one, and some organizational
theorists have.10 What these theorists sometimes have been slow to
recognize, however, is that there is a partial cure for the disease. An
important virtue of the administration of justice by juries and other
impartial tribunals is that it maximizes the extent to which outcomes
depend on the facts of each case and minimizes the influence of personal
favoritism and favor-seeking. Juries in particular are not repeat
players. An adjudicative system treats each case as a tale in which the
defendant has a major role rather than as a short chapter in which he
has a minor part. It reduces the chance that the defendant's interests
will be sacrificed to build capital for the future, repay old debts, or
simply win the approval of co-workers for its own sake.
Plea bargaining promotes inadequate representation for a fourth
reason. Defense attorneys, like other people, do not want to be proven
wrong. A decision to plead guilty, unlike a decision to stand trial,
cannot be proven wrong. A guilty plea not only masks prior errors and
professional deficiencies but also ensures the impregnability of a
lawyer's professional judgment. Once a guilty plea has been entered, no
one can know what result a trial would have reached. From the
defendant's perspective, one can always suppose that the outcome would
have been worse. When an attorney takes a case to trial, by contrast, he
knows (and his client usually knows) what offer or bargaining
opportunity has been declined. At the conclusion of a trial, it may be
evident that the rejection of an offer has cost a defendant several
years of his life. This moment of recognition is unlikely to enhance a
lawyer's self-esteem or make future contact with the client more
pleasant. Nevertheless, the risk of this unhappy moment can be avoided.
A lawyer need only follow what is always the safe and secure course in a
plea bargaining system -- persuade the client to plead guilty.
A fifth reason why a regime of plea bargaining promotes inadequate
representation is its secrecy and unwritten rules. These characteristics
maximize the dangers of inexperience. As one prosecutor observed,
"Anyone who can try a civil case can try a criminal case, but a civil
lawyer is not qualified to evaluate a criminal case. He has no way of
knowing what a criminal case is worth."11 Moreover, the danger is not
simply that an inexperienced lawyer may be unable to distinguish a good
offer from a bad offer. In addition, the lawyer may not know how to get
a good offer. When does a lawyer push too hard and harm his clients
because courthouse insiders conclude that he is a "shotgun who goes off
half-cocked"? When does he fail to push hard enough and harm his clients
because insiders realize that they can take advantage of him? How
"reasonable" is too reasonable, and how "reasonable" is not reasonable
enough? These questions are difficult, and defendants may suffer while
attorneys try to figure them out.
By contrast, trial is an open system -- a system with reasonably
well-defined roles and a system that can be studied, learned, and
eventually mastered. Moreover, even when an inexperienced attorney
founders at trial, the witnesses usually tell their stories in a
coherent fashion; the judge usually gives reasonably accurate
instructions on the law; the jurors usually follow both the evidence and
their consciences; and if the defendant is convicted, the judge imposes
the sentence that he thinks fair. An inexperienced defense lawyer can
harm his clients greatly at trial, but to a far greater extent than plea
negotiation, trial is a system of checks and balances.
There is a sixth way in which the performance of defense attorneys in
a plea bargaining system differs from their performance in an
adjudicative system. A conscientious lawyer in a plea bargaining system
cannot be only an advocate for his client. The lawyer must also be the
point man or woman for a coercive system of justice. It is the defense
attorney who must deliver the message that the client does not have an
unfettered right to trial. It is the defense attorney who must explain
how the plea bargaining leverage works. Some clients may be slow to get
the message, and one public defender observed, "A lawyer shirks his duty
when he does not coerce his client."12 The duty of a conscientious lawyer
is indeed to ensure that his client understands what is at stake. In
performing this duty, the lawyer may be required to use such harsh
language as: "I cannot beat this case. The jury wants your blood. You
will burn if you do not change your plea."13
Although a well-intentioned lawyer who "coerces" his client may be
effective in saving the client from an avoidable penalty, he is likely
to be ineffective in another respect. He is unlikely to inspire his
client's confidence. The client may conclude that the lawyer does not
believe in his case. In a plea bargaining system, even a capable and
conscientious defense attorney is likely to incur the distrust and
resentment of the person whom he seeks to serve. One can envision a
different role for a defense attorney -- a role in which the attorney
could leave the judging to others and be unreservedly on his client's
side. Nevertheless, an attorney could properly assume this role only in
a system that did not penalize the decision to present an adversary
defense.
Perhaps, for some lawyers, the lofty ideals of our profession are an
adequate answer to the temptations that I have described; but I confess
that, were I a defense attorney, these temptations would influence me. I
might not join the ranks of those lawyers who purposely betray their
clients, who appear in hundreds of cases every year and never try any of
them, and who sometimes even deceive their clients in order to persuade
them to plead guilty. Nevertheless, it is a rare case in which a defense
attorney cannot secure a plausible offer from a prosecutor. After
receiving a colorable offer, I could not forget that the alternative to
accepting it would be extra days of work -- work which might or might not
benefit my client but which certainly would prove costly to me.
II
I will address only briefty the second set of reasons why insuring
the effective assistance of counsel is and will remain a dream in our
plea bargaining system. In a system whose structure encourages
inadequate assistance, no effective mechanism exists for determining
whether inadequate assistance has occurred. Nor does it seem likely that
an effective mechanism can be created.
In 1984, after years of neglecting the issue, the Supreme Court
articulated a general standard for judging the effectiveness of counsel.
In Strickland v. Washington14, a defendant who had pleaded guilty
challenged the effectiveness of his counsel at the sentencing proceeding
that followed his plea. The Supreme Court viewed the case as a vehicle
for addressing in sweeping legislative fashion a broad range of issues
likely to arise in effective assistance cases.15 The Court said:
In giving meaning to the [Constitutional] requirement, . . . we must
take its purpose -- to ensure a fair trial -- as the guide. The benchmark
for judging any claim of ineffectiveness must be whether counsel's
conduct so undermined the proper functioning of the adversarial process
that the trial cannot be relied on as having produced a just result.16
In a system in which almost no one receives a trial, the terms of the
Court's long-awaited general formula for resolving claims of ineffective
assistance were limited to trials. Perhaps this limitation reftected the
myopic assumption that an adversarial trial is still the norm in the
American system of criminal justice. The limitation, however, may have
reflected, not the Supreme Court's naivety, but its sophistication. Only
a defendant who has exercised the right to trial has a significant
chance of demonstrating that he has not received the effective
assistance of counsel. Perhaps, for this reason, the Supreme Court
concluded that guilty plea cases could be safely disregarded.
Despite the formal limitation of the Strickland standard to
trials, the proper application of the Court's approach to claims of
ineffective assistance in the guilty plea process seems apparent. The
Strickland Court said:
First, the defendant must show that counsel's performance was
deficient. This requires showing that counsel made errors so serious
that counsel was not functioning as the "counsel" guaranteed by the
Sixth Amendment. Second, the defendant must show that the deficient
performance prejudiced the defense. This requires showing that counsel's
errors were so serious as to deprive the defendant of a fair trial, a
trial whose result is reliable.17
The court added that "[j]udicial scrutiny of counsel's performance
must be highly deferential," that "a court must indulge a strong
presumption that counsel's conduct falls within the wide range of
reasonable professional assistance," and that "[t]he defendant must show
that there is a reasonable probability that, but for counsel's
unprofessional errors, the result of the proceeding would have been
different."18
Strickland imposes a heavy burden on defendants convicted at
trial who challenge the adequacy of the representation that they have
received. At a trial, however, both the attorney's courtroom performance
and the evidence presented by the prosecutor are matters of record. On
rare occasion, a defendant may be able to point to specific misconduct,
demonstrate that it was egregious, and show that competent
representation probably would have altered the outcome. In a guilty plea
case, by contrast, both the attorney's conferences with his client and
his conferences with the prosecutor are secret. The absence of a record
makes it extraordinarily difficult for a defendant to demonstrate that
his plea was unreliable or that counsel's errors were likely to have
altered the outcome. Moreover, it is difficult for a reviewing court to
know what can be expected of an attorney in an unstructured bargaining
situation. As Professor Schulhofer has noted, one can conjure up a
plausible reason for almost any default in a plea bargaining system.19
Strickland's heavy weighing of the scales against claims of
ineffective assistance drives the last nail into the coffin of the
defendant whose inadequate lawyer has led him to plead guilty. But this
last nail hardly matters. Whatever the formula for judging claims of
ineffective assistance and whatever the facts, the defendant who has
been inadequately represented and induced to plead guilty has almost no
chance.
Ineffective representation is far more likely to occur in guilty plea
cases than in trial cases. The weakest members of the defense bar are
not usually the lawyers who put the state to its proof. Committing
serious errors at trial might be an enormous step forward for some
attorneys. Nevertheless, defendants who have pleaded guilty are far less
likely to secure relief on grounds of ineffective representation than
defendants who have been convicted at trial.
This irony is compounded by the fact that, in the Brady
trilogy in 197020 the Supreme Court equated a knowing waiver with a
competently counseled waiver. The Court therefore refused to consider
directly whether the defendants in the three cases before it had
knowingly waived their constitutional rights by entering gnilty pleas.
With rare exceptions, the Court has since permitted defendants who have
pleaded guilty to secure relief only by shouldering the
all-but-impossible burden of demonstrating that they did not receive the
effective assistance of counsel.21
The American system of criminal justice is distinctive in three
respects. First, it makes the kind of justice that a defendant receives
more dependent on the quality of counsel than any other legal system in
the world. Second, it subjects defense attorneys to serious temptations
to disregard their clients' interests. And third, it makes it impossible
to determine whether defendants have received the effective assistance
of counsel. No proposed reform except Professor Schulhofer's bold new
model -- the adversary criminal trial -- holds promise of eliminating these
paradoxes.
* EDS. NOTE: Normally it is the policy of the Review to use female pronouns for the third person singular when the pronoun is used generically. However, at the time this paper was accepted for publication, this policy was not mandatory.
| |